Gibson's Ecological View
of Psychology
from Gregory, Richard L.
(ed.) (1987). The Oxford Companion To The Mind. p. 294. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
GIBSON, JAMES JEROME
(1904-79). A distinguished American experimental psychologist, whose work on
visual perception was and remains unusually influential. Following an
appointment at Smith College, Northampton, Massachusetts, where as a young
professor he was considerably influenced by Kurt Koffka, who had recently
emigrated from Germany, Gibson for many years ran a major department at Cornell
University. His life-work was investigating visual perception of form and
motion; his early work including the discovery that distorting lenses produce
negative (reversed) adaptation to curvature even with free eye-movements. But
his main work was to challenge the approach of Helmholtz and suggest a very
different account of perception.
Gibson first of all moved
away from the traditional experiments with pictures, and what is seen with a
single static eye, towards the observer moving around freely and viewing moving
objects in natural conditions. He was led to this by considering pilots landing
on fields, where the 'flow lines' of motion are important for seeing the
landing-point and estimating height and speed. From such considerations of
'visual flow', and texture gradients, he developed what he called 'Ecological
Optics'. This almost ignored retinal images, and active brain processes, in
favour of regarding perception as 'picking up information from the ambient array
of light'. This is very different from the Helmholtzian notion of perceptions
as Unconscious Inferences from sensory data and knowledge of objects. Gibson
tried to explain object perception by supposing that some 'higher order'
features are invariant with motion and rotation and are 'picked up' with no
perceptual computing or processing being required. His search for such
invariances, and for just what the visual system uses under various conditions
(though this was not Gibson's intention) has proved useful for developing
computer vision. His general philosophy, however, that perception is passive
pickup of information, is hard to follow. His important books are: The
Perception of the Visual World
(1950), and The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems (1966). Much of his work was done with his wife,
Eleanor, a distinguished developmental psychologist.
from Hunt, Morton (1993).
The Story Of Psychology, pp.
466-468, 474-477. New York: Doubleday. (See original for footnotes and
citations.)
pp. 466-468:
There is yet another
modern theory about depth perception, one that is neither specifically neural
nor specifically cognitive. Not that its proponent tactfully combined the two;
on the contrary, he virtually ignored the neural theory and dismissed the cognitive
theories as unnecessary and based on wrong assumptions.
Only a thoroughgoing
maverick would reject a century's worth of depth perception research and claim
to have found a totally different and correct approach. Only a true
nonconformist would assert that we perceive depth neither by neural detection
nor inference from cues but "directly" and automatically. Only a
brash individualist would present a radical epistemology in which the physics
of light is said to be such that what comes to our eyes gives us an accurate,
literal experience of depth, and that we need not interpret what we see because
we see what is as it is.
Such a one was the late
James J. Gibson (1904-1980), whose admirers consider him "the most
important student of visual perception of the twentieth century" and
"the most original theoretician in the world in the psychology of
perception," but whose theory is considered by the majority of perception
specialists "extremely implausible" (one reviewer even called it too
"silly" to merit discussion) and has few advocates.
It did not help Gibson's
cause that as he developed his radical concept of perception, between 1950 and
1980, he became ever more scornful of existing perception theories and of
mainstream psychology in general. Typical of his views are these comments:
"Psychology, or at least American psychology, is a second-rate discipline
. . . The main reason is that it does not stand in awe of its subject matter," and "Psychology
[is] the effort to find answers to the wrong questions; the study of problems
chosen to be convenient to study,
instead ot relevant." Yet
despite his waspish opinions and a severe hearing loss, he was always so
good-natured, engaging, and affable that almost everyone he came in contact
with liked him, and one enthusiastic chronicler describes him as
"fascinating, animated, and lovable."
Gibson, born in a river
town in Ohio and reared in various parts of the Midwest, was the son of a
railroad surveyor. This gave him many a chance to ride the trains and to experience
what became a core element of his theory of visual perception. As he notes in a
brief autobiography, "At the age of eight I knew what the world looked
like from a railroad train and how it seemed to flow inward when seen from the
rear platform and expand outward when seen from the locomotive."
Gibson went to Princeton
University but felt out of place among the club members and preferred to
associate with what he called "the eccentrics." For a while he
vacillated between philosophy and acting (he was wavy-haired, square-jawed, and
good-looking enough for leading roles), but in his senior year he took a course
in psychology and at once heard the call. While doing graduate work in
psychology at Princeton, he came under the influence of behaviorists. In 1928,
however, he received a faculty appointment at Smith, where he met Kurt Koffka,
and, though he did not become a Gestaltist, was much influenced by the
Gestaltist concepts of organization and structure.
For some years, Gibson
was interested in both social psychology and relatively traditional perception
research. Then, during World War II he was asked by the Army Air Corps's
Aviation Psychology Program to develop depth-perception tests for determining
who had the visual aptitudes needed for flying, particularly for making
successful take-offs and landings.
Perhaps because of
Gibson's early experiences on trains, he considered the classical cues to depth
perception, including shadows and perspective, of little worth. In his opinion
they were based on paintings and parlor stereoscopes rather than on
three-dimensional reality, and on static images rather than on movement. What
seemed to him much more useful and realistic were two other kinds of cues:
texture gradient, like the uniforrnly changing roughness of the runway as seen
by a pilot during the final leg of an approach; and motion perspective, or the
flow of changing relationships among objects as one moves through the
environment, including all that a pilot sees during take-offs and landings.
These cues soon became, and are today, accepted components of the cue-based
theory of depth perception.
Gibson's Air Corps work
held the germ of his later view. The crucial mechanism in depth perception (in
all perception, according to Gibson) is not the retinal image, with all its
cues, but the changing flow of relationships among objects and their surfaces
in the environment that the perceiver moves through.
This concept came to
dominate Gibson's thinking during the 1950s and 1960s, when he did a
considerable amount of research at Cornell that tested his belief in texture
gradients. In some experiments he placed diffusing milkglass between an
observer and textured surfaces; in others he dilated the observer's eyes to
prevent sharp focus on texture; in still others he cut PingPong balls in half
and made goggles of them so that what his subjects saw was foglike, without
surfaces or volume. From these and other experiments, plus a careful
consideration of his research on air-crew testing and training, Gibson came to
reject texture gradients and to stress movement by the observer through the
environment as the key to depth perception. However large or small the
movement, it results in changes in the optic arrayÑthe structured pattern of
light reaching the eye from the environmentÑsuch as is suggested in this
drawing:
Figure
31.
How
optic array conveys depth
The optic array, rich in
information as seen from any point, becomes infinitely richer with movement by
the observer. Even minor movements of the head change the array, transforming
what is seen of an object and the relationships among objects, and yielding
optic flow of one kind or another. Gibson came to believe that there is enough,
and more than enough, information in the optic array and flow to convey depth and
distance directly, without the need of mental calculation or inference from
cues.
This is how Gibson
explained depth perception in his sweeping "ecological" theory of
"direct perception." The pity is that Gibson, the outsider and
eccentric, who, according to a fellow psychologist, was always "terribly
tough and uncompromising," felt obliged to throw out the baby with the
bathwater. For it is possible to acknowledge both the neural and cognitive
views of depth perception as correctly explaining different aspects of the
phenomenon and the Gibsonian view as supplementary to them. But it wasn't
possible for James J. Gibson.
pp. 475-477:
The direct or ecological
perception theory of Gibson and his followers attempts to explain not only
depth perception, as sketched above, but visual perception in general. Gibson's
doctrine that the perceiver's movement through the environment produces a
constantly changing optic array is the heart not only of his explanation of
depth perception but of his account of form, size, distance, and motion
perception.
Gibson's exposition of
his theory in his 1979 book, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, is abstruse, argumentative, and difficult to
follow, in part because he uses many neologisms. But its limited acceptance by
perception psychologists may have been more the result of his dismissal of
nearly everything that had been achieved in perception research by others. A
typical Gibson comment (from a posthumous article):
The
conclusions that can be reached from a century of research on perception are
insignificant. The knowledge gained from a century of research on sensation is
incoherent. We have no adequate theory of perception, and what we have found in
the search for sensations is a mixed batch of illusions, physiological
curiosities, and bodily feelings. The implications are discouraging. A fresh
start has to be made on the problem of perception.
Gibson's recommendation
as to where to make that fresh start sounds sensible enough: with the question
(echoing Koffka) "Why do things look as they do?" and continuing:
How do
we see where we are in the environment? How do we see whether or not we are
moving and, if we are, where we are going? How do we see what things are good
for? How do we see how to do things?
To make a truly fresh
start, Gibson discarded most of the fundamental assumptions that philosophers
and psychologists have always made about visual perception. Among them:
sensations are the basis of perceptions; stimuli from the outside impinge on
the organism; the organism produces responses; the brain processes, integrates,
and interprets the information; the proper study of vision begins with the
retina and the brain; optical motion is something for which the visual system
must compensate; the environment is represented only in part by the information
on the retina; perception depends in large part on inference; and so on and on.
A new broom, James J. Gibson.
In place of the
assumptions he swept away, Gibson offers his own theory, which is more
philosophic than empirical, more conceptual than data-based, and hard to grasp.
All the same, he came to his views by means of experiments, first on motion
perception and then on perception of form and other real-world qualities. As
already noted, the first glimmer of the truth appeared to him in the course of
his Air Corps research, of which he said:
We
learned more about the perception of objects, I think, than we would ever have
done by running standard laboratory experiments on form-perception. For one
thing, I got a nagging suspicion that nobody ever really sees a flat form in
life, that is, a picture of a thing. One sees a continuous family of
perspective transformations, an infinity of forms, that somehow specifies the
solid shape of the object.
From this, he went on
later to reject not only all research based on pictures and illusions but all
theorizing about perception as the result of the mind's interpretation of the
imperfect information in the two-dimensional pictures on the retina:
Eventually
I came to realize how unlike the pictorial mode of perception is from the
natural one. The former is perception at second hand; the latter is perception
at first hand. The framed optic array coming from a picture to the eye is quite
unlike the natural optic array coming from the world to an eye . . . Eyes
evolved so as to see the world, not a picture. Since this became clear to me I
have tried to give up any use whatever of the term "retinal image."
Gibson concluded, as we
have seen, that the optic array contains all the information about the real
world that we need. He admitted that our knowledge of the world is limited by
the characteristics of the nervous system, but those characteristics, he
maintained, were determined by evolutionary adaptation to the world; we are aware
of all those properties of the environment that we need to be aware of.
Evolution produced a perceptual system in each creature that enables it to
directly recognize the qualities in the environment that will be useful to
itÑin Gibsonian language, its "affordances," or what uses the
properties of any entity will afford the creature. So things look edible,
drinkable, walk-onable, swim-inable, and so on, in relation to the observer's
size and physical equipment.
Perception, in short, is
not a process of interpreting a degraded retinal image but a direct and truthful experience of reality by means of the
optic array and optic flow. This, for Gibson, is the central mechanism of
perceptionÑnot the neural events documented by Hubel and Wiesel (whose work he
regarded as irrelevant), and not cognitive processes, which he considered to be
based on erroneous and artificial assumptions.
Direct perception is also
Gibson's answer to Berkeley. We know that the world is out there and exists
independently of us because as we move through the environment, we see things
in an ever-changing way and yet we experience their continuity, reality, and
independence of us as perceivers. So do all other animals; only philosophers
ever doubted that the world really is what it seems to be. Gibson's theory of
visual perception thus ventured far beyond vision into epistemology.
And further. By the end
of his life, Gibson had come to believe that perception was the cornerstone of
all psychology and that his theory of it could bring about radical change in
many areas of the science. Such concepts as mind, consciousness, learning, and
drive would be replaced by an ecological psychology based on creatures'
awareness of the useful and dangerous properties of places, events, and
objects, and on their organization and control of their actions to achieve
desirable results in the real world.
What progress Gibson
might have made toward this empyrean goal we can never know; he died only two
years after publishing The Ecological Approach, and although some of his ideas about visual
perception, notably optic flow, have become part of accepted doctrine, neither
these nor his more ambitious notions have brought about a revolution in
perception, much less psychology in general.
It is a pity that Gibson
became so intolerant and evangelistic; his concept of optic flow, though it
does not make unnecessary much that he thought it did, is certainly of value,
but his extremism has kept his contribution from being as widely accepted as it
deserves to be.
[By way of contrast, here
is a representative cognitive view of perception, Irving Rock's theory of
perception as problem-solving and inference-making starting from an
impoverished retinal image]
pp. 474-475
Rock spent many years
devising and conducting other experiments to test the hypothesis that, more
often than not, perception requires higher-level processes than those taking
place in the visual cortex. These studies led him, finally, to his present
thesis that "perception is intelligent in that it is based on operations
similar to those that characterize thought."
And indeed, says Rock,
perception may have led to thought; it may be the evolutionary link between
low-level sensory processes in primitive organisms and high-level cognitive
processes in more complex forms of life. If what the eye sees, he argues, is an
ambiguous and distortion-prone representation of reality, some mechanism had to
evolve to yield reliable and faithful knowledge of that reality. In his words,
"Intelligent operations may have evolved in the service of
perception."
This is not to say that
all perception is thoughtlike; Rock specifically cites the waterfall illusion
as explicable in low-level neural terms. But most facts about motion perception
and other kinds of perception seem to him to require high-level processes.
Unconscious inference, as in our use of texture gradient cues to sense
distance, is only one of them. Description that results in interpretation is
another. In the ambiguous old hag-young woman figure by Boring, what one sees
is not the result of simply recognizing an image but of describing to oneself
what a particular curve is like: like a nose or like a cheek. Many perceived
forms or objects are not instantly recognizable; recognizing what they are
comes about through such a process.
Perception also often
calls for problem solving of one sort or another. One hardly thinks of
perception as the solving of problems, but Rock has marshaled a considerable
amount of evidenceÑmuch from earlier studies by others, some from his own
original experimentsÑto show that in many cases we seek a hypothesis to account
for what we see, weigh that hypothesis against other possibilities, and choose
the one that seems to solve the problem of making sense of what we see. All of
this usually takes place in a fraction of a second.
One example: In a
laboratory phenomenon known since the time of Helmholtz, if a wavelike curvcd
line is passed horizontally behind a slit, as in this figure,
Figure
34.
Anorthoscopic
perception: The dot moves up and down but the mind figures out what is
happening.
most observers first see
it as a small element moving up and down, but after a while some of them will
suddenly see the sinuous line moving at right angles to and behind the
aperture. What produces their altered and correct perception? Rock found that
one clue they use is the changing slope of the line as it passes the slit;
another is the end of the curved line, if it comes into view. Such clues
suggest to the mind an alternative hypothesisÑthat a curve is moving past the
slit horizontally, rather than that a small element is moving up and down. This
hypothesis is so much better that the mind accepts it and sees the line as it
really is.
Rock sums up his theory
as follows:
On a
theoretical level, at least according to the theory presented here, both
perception and thought entail reasoning. In some cases, generalizations or
rules are arrived at in perception by induction. These rules are then used
deductively as premises from which inferences are drawn. Perception in some
cases can be characterized as the result of creative problem solving, in the
sense of searching for the grounds (or internal solution) from which a specific
interpretation follows. Perception entails decisions, just as does thought.
Operations that culminate in perceptual experience are of the same kind that
characterize thinking.